Monday, May 30, 2011

The “Lazy Aristotle” Fallacy

Otherwise known as “confusing the natural with the common” or “the ‘normal’ equivocation”. The word ‘normal’ signifies at least two different terms or concepts that are entirely distinct in themselves, even though they might be related in very fundamental ways (hence the confusion). Here are the two senses I have in mind and as I would distinguish them:

Normal1 = what is the most frequent; what is common; whatever happens the majority of the time.

Normal2 = what is normative (i.e., what should or ought to be the case).

Here is an example that at once shows the difference between these two senses and also that there is *no* reason to think that they must coincide.

Suppose the world’s water supply is contaminated in such a way that it makes every single dog have three legs or, if a certain dog has yet to be born, it is born with only three legs. It seems to me that in the sense of normal1, the following statement would be true:

(1) It is normal for dogs to have only three legs.

If the ‘normal’ in (1) means frequent, common, or what happens the majority of the time, then of course it is true. How could it be the case that each and every dog has only three legs but and it not be ‘common’ for them to have only three legs?

But clearly, even though (1) might be true in the normal1 sense it is patently false if taken in the normal2 sense. That is, even though it might be the case that all dogs have only three legs, it most certainly is not the case that all dogs should or ought to have only three legs. On the contrary, as Aristotle would put it: it is the nature of a dog to have four legs, and therefore all dogs should have four legs.

The basic upshot is this. Suppose that some act F happens most of the time. Nothing follows about whether F should happen most of the time. And vice-versa. Suppose F ought to happen. Nothing follows about whether F will in fact happen all of the time or even most times.

Here are some more putative cases where normal1 and normal2 most certainly do not coincide:

From what I hear, binge drinking is not uncommon on college campuses, yet it seems that binge drinking should be uncommon.

Binge drinking is at best normal1 but not normal2.

Prior to the Civil War, slavery in the South was very common, yet it should not have been.

Slavery was normal1 but surely not normal2.

In 1930’s Germany anti-Semitism might have been common, yet if it was, it should not have been.

Anti-Semitism may have been normal1 but surely not normal2.

What is especially vexing about the fallacy is that you often hear people using some fact about what is normal1 as evidence to think that the act in question is normal2, which either equivocates on the two senses or begs the very question at hand or both. Here is an example:

(2) Homosexuality is wrong because it is not normal.

The inference here is something like this:

(3) Homosexuality is not normal.

(4) Therefore, homosexuality is wrong.

If ‘normal’ means normal1, then this argument is invalid. As we have seen before, just because F is not common, it does not mean that F-ing ought to not take place.

If ‘normal’ here means normal2, then sure enough the argument would be valid, but then it would be begging the question. For to say that F-ing ought to not take place is tantamount to saying that F-ing is wrong.

I call this the “Lazy Aristotle Fallacy” because Aristotle was prone to thinking that what happens “either always or for the most part” was indicative of a thing’s nature, where “nature” here is to be understood as the “what it is to be” of a thing—its essence (as opposed to “that place people go when they go camping.”) Since Aristotle was thinking of natures as essences, they are the kinds of things that ground normative claims. But, as we have seen, it is not at all clear the connection between what is common, what is natural, and what ought to happen, much less how we ought to move from one to the next, even if it is very common for us to do so.

All this to say that I think this fallacy is nothing short of a rampant intellectual disease that has infected most of the human “sciences” (e.g., psychology, cultural anthropology, sociology, psychiatry, and the like). I also think that failing to recognize this fallacy is one of the major confusions behind the ever shifting faces of the various forms of relativism.

2 Comments:

Blogger Louis said...

At first as I was reading I found this to be obvious to the point of almost being uninteresting. Like, any clear-thinking adult should understand this. But as I read on I began to realize how often I commit this fallacy and by the end I realized that, as you pointed out, whole fields are founded on it.

On that note, though, it seems shrwed behavioral scientists own up to as much but don't see any other way of determining what is normative besides what is common.

Well, I suppose there are those religiously motivated psychologists with MDivs and MFTs who derive some sense of normativity from their religious and philosophical beliefs or from those of their religious or philosophical community.

Why do those folks always seem less qualified and less scientific?

How does Rosemead do?

9:49 AM  
Blogger Derek said...

“On that note, though, it seems shrwed behavioral scientists own up to as much but don't see any other way of determining what is normative besides what is common.”

Unless we (re)introduce teleological reflection (along with all of its metaphysical baggage) as a legitimate methodological tool in scientific enquiry. For example, suppose the three-legged dog event were to take place. How do we know that it wouldn’t be natural? Well (I hear Aristotle saying), we’d notice how awkward it is for a dog to perform seemingly ordinary tasks—like running and walking and probably mating. Heck, we’d even be able to partially infer the “naturalness” of the missing leg just by thinking about the structural elements of the dog’s body. The missing leg would appear to be a “natural” fit that aids in the “overall natural functioning (flourishing) of the species”. But, employing teleological reasoning ultimately leads to such “unscientific” statements like, “the purpose of the leg is help the dog run effectively, and the purpose of the dogs’ running effectively is ultimately to flourish as a species.”

And it gets worse:

“Well, what’s the purpose of the flourishing of the species?” Aristotle would say that the purpose is the same as the flourishing. That is, the life characteristic of dog is an intrinsic good that is an end in itself.

The Christian, on the other hand, would be uncomfortable with the pagan notion of a good intrinsic to nature, and would say that the “purpose” of the flourishing of a species is (ultimately) to glorify God.

But the naturalist must think that all of this is nonsense. “Purpose”, “intrinsic good”?—there’s no such thing in a world of nothing but matter and energy.

So, I say, let the naturalist keep her naturalism, so long as she keeps her mouth shut about what ought to be the case.

“Well, I suppose there are those religiously motivated psychologists with MDivs and MFTs who derive some sense of normativity from their religious and philosophical beliefs or from those of their religious or philosophical community.

Why do those folks always seem less qualified and less scientific?”

Any less “scientific” than Freud or Skinner? The difference is superficial and/or a matter of fashion.

Also, I think the confusion between the normal (common) and normal (normative) is behind the stupidity of Quine’s suggestion that epistemology could be a branch of empirical psychology. In the first place, this presupposes that the claims of empirical psychology are themselves already and independently justified (which is the very question of epistemology). And second it suggests that somehow by figuring about *how* it is we in fact form beliefs we will thereby know what it is for a belief to be *justified* (a thoroughgoing *normative* issue). But this is silly. Suppose we ask a fortuneteller how she knows she’s *justified* in believing her predictions and in response she whips out her tarot cards and shows us *how* to read and shuffle them. Or further, imagine a logician telling us that affirming the consequent is a valid (viz.—a *licit*) form of reasoning because most people do it.

2:20 PM  

Post a Comment

<< Home

Creative Commons License
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs 3.0 United States License.