Monday, December 18, 2017

if a certain natural deduction system is complete, then it is complete without material implication.

Consider 𝒲, the system of natural deduction articulated by the Howard-Snyders and Wasserman (2013). After introducing seventeen rules, some of which include Conditional Proof (CP), two forms of Reductio ad absurdum (RAA), Modus Ponens (MP), Simplification (Simp), Conjunction (Conj), Addition (Add), Commutation (Com), Double Negation (DN), and  Disjunctive Syllogism (DS), they introduce the rule of
    Material Implication (mi): 𝒫 βŠƒ 𝒬  βˆ· ¬𝒫 v 𝒬  
and they do so with the following justification:
Without material implication, our proof system would lack the capacity to prove valid every argument that is valid according to the truth table method. (p. 380)
One way to understand what the Howard-Snyders and Wasserman are sayings goes as follows: With (mi), 𝒲 can prove sentences of the form ¬𝒫 v 𝒬 from sentences of the form 𝒫 βŠƒ 𝒬, and vice-versa. Or
    𝒫 βŠƒ 𝒬 βŠ’π’² ¬𝒫 v 𝒬  
and
    ¬𝒫 v 𝒬 βŠ’π’²  𝒫 βŠƒ 𝒬
However, if we were to remove (mi) from 𝒲, perhaps forming the natural deduction system 𝒲*, we could not prove ¬𝒫 v 𝒬 from 𝒫 βŠƒ 𝒬 and vice versa. That is:
    𝒫 βŠƒ 𝒬 βŠ¬π’²*  ¬𝒫 v 𝒬
and
    ¬𝒫 v 𝒬 βŠ¬π’²*  𝒫 βŠƒ 𝒬
We will now show that neither one is trueβ€”viz., we will show that
    𝒫 βŠƒ 𝒬 βŠ’π’²*  ¬𝒫 v 𝒬
and
    ¬𝒫 v 𝒬 βŠ’π’²*  𝒫 βŠƒ 𝒬
And we will do this by using only the inference rules of 𝒲*, which, as we’ve said is any one of 𝒲 but (mi). We shall begin with
    𝒫 βŠƒ 𝒬 βŠ’π’²*  ¬𝒫 v 𝒬
Consider a substitutional instance of 𝒫 βŠƒ 𝒬:
    A βŠƒ B
We shall show that
    A βŠƒ B βŠ’π’²*  Β¬A v B
Proof:
1. A βŠƒ B                                βŠ’π’²*  Β¬A v B
2.     Β¬(Β¬A v B)                        Assume for RAA
3.         A                                 Assume for CP
4.         B                                 1, 3, MP
5.         B v Β¬A                        4, Add
6.         Β¬A v B                        5, Com
7.         Β¬A v B β€’ Β¬(Β¬A v B)    6, 2, Conj
8.   Β¬A v B                              2-7, RAA         
And now for
    ¬𝒫 v 𝒬 βŠ’π’²*  𝒫 βŠƒ 𝒬
Consider a substitutional instance of ¬𝒫 v 𝒬:
    Β¬A v B
We shall show that
    Β¬A v B βŠ’π’²*  A βŠƒ B
Proof:
1. Β¬A v B      βŠ’π’²*  A βŠƒ B
2.     A             Assume for CP
3.     ¬¬A        2, DN
4.     B             1, 3, DS
5.  A βŠƒ B       2-4, CP
What this shows is that, contra the Howard-Snyders and Wasserman, if their system of natural deduction is complete, viz. if it such that any sentence 𝒫 is a valid inference from a given set of premises, then there is a proof of 𝒫 from those same set of premises, it would still be complete without (mi).
References
Howard-Snyder, D. and F., and Wasserman, R. (2013). The Power of Logic (5th Ed.) New York: McGraw Hill.

Monday, December 04, 2017

on William Lane craig on whether A logically implies B.

William Lane Craig (β€œTrinity Monotheism once more...”) says that,
Moreover, Howard-Snyder seems to assume that truth-making is closed under logical implication […] But that assumption is false. For example, β€œ[a cat] has retractable claws” implies that β€œGrass is green,” since both are true, but they obviously have different truth-makers. (Β§3)
I have nothing to say about whether truth-making is closed under logical implication. I do have something to say about Craig’s argument that
    A    A cat has retractable claws. 
(logically) implies
    B    Grass is green.
β€œSince”, Craig says, β€œboth are true”. Craig is almost certainly confused here.
By my lights, a sentence/statement/proposition 𝒫 logically implies 𝒬 , abbreviated 𝒫 ⊨ 𝒬, just in case 𝒬 is a logical consequence of 𝒫, which is to say that there is no truth-value assignment or β€œvaluation” in which 𝒫 is true and 𝒬 is false. But, if you were to put A and B on a truth table, there will be one line in which A is true and B is false. Hence A does not logically imply B, or
    A ⊭ B
It may be, however, that all that Craig intended is to say is that, given that A and B are true, A β€œmaterially” implies B, or A βŠƒ B. Indeed, since there is no truth value assignment in which A and B are true and A βŠƒ B if false, the former logically implies the latter, or
    A & B ⊨ A βŠƒ B
Note, however, that this doesn’t affect my previous point. It’s one thing to say that,
    given A & B, the material conditional A βŠƒ B is true,
and it’s another to say that,
    given A & B, A logically implies B.
The former says something true about the conjunction, A & B, in relation to the material conditional, A βŠƒ B, whereas the latter says something false about the conjunction, A & B, and its relation to another relation: the relation between A and B per se.
Now, by my understanding,
Relation β„› is closed under logical implication just in case, if x stands in relation β„›  to 𝒫, and if 𝒫 logically implies 𝒬, that is 𝒫 ⊨ 𝒬, then x stands in relation β„› to 𝒬.
For example: some have thought, but many deny, that the knows that relation between an agent and a proposition is closed under logical implication. This view has the consequence that, if Craig knows that A, then Craig knows that: either A or Β¬B, for A ⊨ A v Β¬B. Notice that if the knows that relation were closed under logical implication, and we understood logical implication as β€œmaterial” implication, then those who think that the knows that relation is closed under logical implication would be saddled with the view that, if Craig knows A, then Craig knows B, for A βŠƒ B. As dubious as the view that the knows that relation is closed under logical implication might be, it's not that dubious.
Similarly, if we suppose that the makes true relation is closed under logical implication, then this would require only that, e.g., if x makes it true that A, then x makes it true that: either A or Β¬B, for again A ⊨ A v Β¬B. It would not require that, if x is makes it true that A, then x makes it true that B, as A ⊭ B, and this despite the fact that A and B are both true. In summary, then, it appears that Craig’s argument against the view that the makes true relation is closed under logical implication rests upon the following false conditional: If A and B, then A logically implies B.
Creative Commons License
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs 3.0 United States License.